![]() |
Truth of JH’s “creative renewal” part 8 of “Habermas and Truth” |
||
gary e. davis
October 4, 2003 / June 2, 2014 |
|||
It’s clear from “Truth and Justification” (i.e., the section of “Richard Rorty’s Pragmatic Turn,” OPC) that “what is held-to-be-true” (338) pertains for Habermas to lifeworld understanding. So, when he ends the penultimate section of “Some Further Clarifications of the Concept of Communicative Rationality” by referring to “the irrefutably unconditional character of what is held-to-be-true...” (ibid.), he’s referring to the lifeworld (as he is throughout that section of “Some Further...” on “Communicative Rationality and Linguistic World Disclosure” (333-8). In discussion of his Rorty essay, I relativized the notion of unconditionality to (1) discursive finitude, at the level of scientific discourse; and to (2) “bedrock” dependencies of the lifeworld at the level of immaturity (childhood) or illiteracy. Relative to a notion of truth that mediates lifeworld and discourse, JH is writing falsely that there is an unconditional character to what is held-to-be-true, let alone an irrefutable character.
The point of this indication is to relativize the power (a-rational) to [linguistic] rationality. While irrationality is negatively relativized to rationality, the “function” is, “in a certain sense, a-rational” (336-7). “Function” [336] evinces from the “power” of language. [One might argue that this is linguistic relativism, which is untenable in light of cognitive science. But who would claim that language itself has intentionality? Only minds are intentional. The power expressed through language is of intelligence altogether, employing linguisticality that provides for interpersonal rationality, but reason/intelligence cannot be validly equated with interpersonally-efficacious rationality. John Searle has long ago shown that philosophy of language is a mode of philosophy of mind.] Next, he says (weirdly interesting!):
[Since his OPC discussion hasn’t been focused on Heidegger—unlike Philosophical Discourse of Modernity a decade earlier, confronting those Frenchmen—mentioning Heidegger here is symptomatic of an inescapability of Heidegger’s ghost in German philosophy. Heidegger does not equate his sense of language to what’s linguistic. In On the Way to Language, language is sometimes understood as a verb (“language languages”). Articulation belongs to the potential, then capability, of intelligence altogether or to reason. Creative renewal evinces from our being Of Languaging, so to speak. MH’ s “destining of being” is an onto-historical notion, analogous—but not equivalent— to the anthropologicity of Our humanity.] Two pages back, when JH is making an explicit point about the “horizon”ality of the lifeworld (again, as also at TCA-2; 120-6, passim.), he writes:
But isn’t “operate through the medium of language” the same as saying: “we can use it as a means of communication”? No, the two are not the same. What’s the difference? JH is interested in the difference. [Habermas wouldn’t agree, but good individuation of intelligence shapes one’s relationship to linguistic means, as well as having been shaped my linguistic interaction. The mirrorplay of ontogeny is inestimably rich, yet it’s an ontogeny of intelligence altogether, which is also linguistic, such that the linguisticality of our lives is intelligently employed. The “language that is never at our disposal” is our constitutive capability—which, as singular term, is a trope for the manifold of capabilities that one becomes. Therefore, “we always operate through the medium of language.”] Here’s the complete passage from JH without ellipses [but with my added comment]:
The lifeworld as a whole has a horizonality which is “this Being-in-the-World.” It can be “illustrated by the strange semitransparence of a language,” yet this is different from saying that in-the-world-being can be illustrated by the strange semitransparence of language itself, as such.
[The semitransparence is a de-temporalized holism; in-the-world-being expresses ontogenically-lived time in the phenomenality of presence. That simitransparence illustrates the constitutivity of action by the ontogeny of intelligence or capability or reason.]
So, earlier “world-disclosing interpretive knowledge” (in light of the world as a whole) becomes “world-interpreting linguistic knowledge” in coming to grips (such that revisions, in light of renewal, are far more than automatic). What’s the difference there? [It’s the difference between enhancing general capability and enriching shareable articulation.] Is world-disclosing interpretive knowledge futural? [yes]; world-interpreting linguistic knowledge present-centered?; and revisions reconstructive? A futural present (disclosive-to-interpretive) comes to grips, in light of which linguistic self-understanding becomes revised? [I’m stretching to find a constructive stance in JH’s brief formulations.]
Bor-ing. [I’m so bad. Peirce’s abduction was relative to scientific contexts: inferring to the best explanation, which is promoted, then educed, through prospective conceptualization. But problem-solving is not the fundamental motive for creativity. Not even problem-finding is the fundamental motive. Children don’t play imaginatively because they are trying to solve problems. Problems inevitably arise, and solving them is grandly conducive to growing capability. Yet, the motive to explore is born from intrinsic curiosity, which is easily lost in conformist parenting, bad education, consumerism, etc. Creative renewal is partly about retrieving oneself in one’s potential for being.] From whence does the stimulation come, from failing and faltering? I feel like I’m back at Jürgen’s office hours, 1980, explaining to him that the emancipatory interest can’t be equiprimordial with other interests of knowledge because a successful emancipation dissolves the interest, while satisfaction of practical interests leads to more practical interest. Therefore, the emancipatory interest must be a deformation of some other interest (One doesn’t just get more practical in freedom; the emancipatory interest isn’t a deformed practical interest). I, at the time, looked to his essay on Hegel’s Jena period, and told him that the emancipatory interest looks like a deformed self-formative interest. He was very interested in this, not surprisingly, because (I suppose) I was locating the real basis of his own concept of emancipatory interest (with a man whose youthful dissertation had been on Schelling!).
[However, an emancipatory interest is pervasive in Heidegger’s lectures and thinking. Habermas’s anger toward Heidegger, 1959, was the anger of a man who had been deeply influenced by an emancipatory interest in German thought through Heidegger, as well as others. Habermas felt deeply betrayed—falsely informed, but genuinely felt, I don’t doubt—because Heidegger’s emancipatory interest, as it was understood at that time, was so important to contemporary German thought, thus to Habermas’s development. Implicit to Romanticism is emancipatory interest in giving self formative interest freedom.]
Such was Heidegger’s critical burden in sketching a “history of Being” as concealment of “aletheia,” lifelong love so alive in futural, flourishing horizons of poetic thinking.
But also, reason is the capacity for bypassing totalizing power in the first place, thanks to capable-enough individuation (excellent childhood and education). But given the totalizing power, reason is the capacity for knowing that, too. Total linguistification of reason is Logos at work. Enabling the originative efficacy of mindfulness faces a history of intellectual hegemony that confounds creative potential.
...which comes back to haunt Hegel in the Absolute Concept. [A “transcendental” subject is not as such totalizing! Its accomplishment may be non-totalizing; and still be modeled as transcendental subject apart from a Kantian mental paradigm. I confess that I never read Kant rigorously because—as a nubile doctoral student—I was entranced with Husserl’s Formal and Transcendental Logic. This was before meeting Heidegger's critique of Kant and Husserl.] The realm of Ideas in German Idealism is appropriated as implicitly the capacity of intelligence itself. And Plato lived on in the Kantian mandarins of Weimar, before German capital’s Fürher tried to reincarnate Holy Roman Empire. [Critique of metaphysics was understood by Heidegger, even in the 1920s—ex-Catholic theologian of the German mandarins that he was—as a critique of ontotheological power, which was to become emancipatory educational leadership, had not German capital reigned.]
[As they say, that’s the pot calling the kettle black. Let us think about the happening of Truth.] No. What, for Heidegger, is the Happening of the history of Being? Habermas is nowhere near the neighborhood of Heidegger’s immanent way of thinking. How difficult it is to break free of logocentrism through the linguistic paradigm. Heidegger’s “epochs of Being” are matters of the deconstruction of metaphysicalism, Of his sense of truth as [emancipatory] unconcealment, originating in pre-Platonic “a-letheia,” un-closure, un-self-concealing, which Heidegger displays in renewing kinds of intimacy with dis-closure: so-called poetic thinking.
I believe that sober conduct is a good thing. [Condolences for the burden unrelieved, which traces deeply into the intellectual history of Germany that Habermas’s career has so richly sought to redeem.]
Next: “‘creative reason and health of nations” Be fair. © 2017, g. e. davis. |
|||