![]() |
a note on pragmatics of justification part 7 of “Habermas and Truth” |
||
gary e. davis October 3, 2003 / June 1, 2014 |
|||
At the bottom of page 371 (OPC), Habermas wants to show how all the pieces of his case may accord as a singular argumentation sketch. Again, JH is providing a pragmatic theory of justification (and application), not a pragmatic theory of truth (though a pragmatic theory of truth can be derived from my modified version of his argumentation, an appropriative theory of truth). [I didn’t do a derivation, but that kind of work—in a workbook mode—is indirectly exemplified by “In virtue of ethical pragmatics.” I would work through numerous essays by Habermas in the exploratory way I worked there, then later constellate the explorations. That would be a lot of work, just to do revision of Habermas’s modeling. Someday, perhaps.]
You recall that I focused on this earlier, but I want to add a new dimension to JH’s assertion here. By “actor,” JH means, of course, a person or participant in activity or carrying through action. But JH’s theory of action types (TCA-1) includes dramaturgical action, such that we are always, to some degree, actors in self representation of our lives (subjectivities, according to JH, but I will give richer meaning to dramaturgical action than does JH—not today [but that's very developed by now, offline]—in full accord with what JH means by dramaturgical). The pragmatic importance of this presently is that the actor is primarily understood relative to action—persons as action-interested and action-oriented, but the self investment in pragmatic action is far more than Habermas apparently discerns, due to the inappropriately supplementary status that he gives to dramaturgical action. The dramaturgical action type tends to become the central one in individuating lives; other action types tend to become supplemental. But I know that this may easily seem to suggest an egoistic view of action; it is not this.
JH claims that he’s “bringing together partial statements,” but he hasn’t earlier claimed that “there is a practical necessity to rely intuitively on what is unconditionally held-to-be-true,” unless one reads his earlier reference to behavioral certainties as meaning just that. (His earlier “presupposition” of ideal conditions has now become “supposition,” as I recommended earlier.) [Confusing here is that behavioral certainties are factical presumptions, while unconditionality in discourse is an idealization. Only a preconventional, if not illiterate, mind would regard factical presumptions as unconditional. I don’t understand why JH finds preconventional presumption reflected in post-conventional idealization. But this is all resolvable for an appropriate pragmatics of truth. However, I don’t find Habermas providing enough basis for appropriation.]
So perhaps JH would see his entire theory of validity as a coherence theory of truth. In any case, discursants will bring to mind as rich of a sense of validation or truth-finding as they need. Participants decide the degree of idealization that’s appropriate, which is a matter of the scale of interest or questioning of relevant Truth, not only the scale of conditionality in justification of factual claims and/or freedom of constraint in inquiry. The remainder of Habermas’ essay (OPC 372-77) continues his critique of Rorty, so his pragmatic of justification, as it stands for him, becomes largely critical application, and is worthwhile reading—critical exemplification—for that reason. But my interest is, has been, and remains the philosophical pragmatics as such, and JH doesn’t return to this anymore in his essay. So it’s time to move on. Next: “Truth of JH’s ‘creative renewal’” Be fair. © 2014, g. e. davis. |
|||